Hilbert Program: Consistency vs Soundness
I have been wondering why exactly Hilbert asked for a decidable, complete, and consistent set of axioms for mathematics, rather than a decidable, complete, and sound set of axioms.
Consistency being: it is impossible to derive a contradiction from the axioms.
Sound being: the axioms are all true
Intuitively, it seems like you want the axioms to be sound, rather than merely consistent. For example, if we have a decidable, complete, and consistent set of axioms, but one of the axioms is that $exists x exists y x + y not = y + x$, then that would not seem to be a very useful set of axioms about arithmetic. Or at least, it doesn't coincide with our intuition that addition is commutative ... we would intuitively say that that axiom is false.
So, I am trying to make sense why Hilbert was looking for a consistent set of axioms, rather than a sound set. Doing some research and thinking into this, I came up with several different explanations. I was wondering if someone could look at these and tell me if any of them actually make sense.
The axioms having some property, and knowing that the axioms have some property are two different things. So, maybe Hilbert actually was looking for a sound set of axioms, but in terms of what we would be able to prove about the axioms, he was 'merely' looking for a consistency proof. In other words, Hilbert was looking for a decidable, complete, sound, and provably consistent set of axioms (and, I assume also provably complete and provably decidable)
Hilbert was just much more concerned with consistency rather than soundness. Consistency is of course crucial: if the set is not consistent, you can derive any statement, and the whole foundation falls apart. Moreover, if you start with some 'obviously true' statements like the Peano axioms, then in order to keep the system consistent while we're adding more and more axioms, most likely the system will remain sound as well. So, as long as we make sure that things remain consistent, the set probably remains sound as well.
Hilbert (and others at the time) were concerned about the very notion of 'mathematical truth': what is it, really? For example, things are true in Euclidian geometry that are not true in non-Euclidian geometry ... and it makes little sense to insist that one of them is 'more mathematically true' than the other. So, maybe we should say that the very axioms of a system define what is true in that system ... and that there is no notion of 'truth' beyond that; we don't step outside the system, and use some other measure of truth in order to declare: "Yes, those axioms are true", or "No, actually, that one axiom is not true". Instead, to Hilbert, the axiom set being 'sound' and 'consistent' was just one and the same. Indeed, whatever can be proven from a consistent set of axioms is thereby true, so likewise 'provable' and 'true' are the same as well. (I suspect there is a link with Logical Positivism here?) In an online paper "Hilbert's Programme", C. Smorynski states (top of p.7) that Hilbert said that:
If the arbitrarily given axioms do not contradict each other with all their consequences, then they are true and the things defined by the axioms exist. This is for me the criterion of truth and existence.
(Unfortunately, Smorynski does not give the exact reference for this ... it seems like it could come from Hilbert's Grundlagen Der Geometrie ... but some translation of course ... I would love to have an exact reference for this quote .. if it is indeed a quote)
So, which of these explanations is the correct one .. if any?
logic math-history foundations philosophy
|
show 11 more comments
I have been wondering why exactly Hilbert asked for a decidable, complete, and consistent set of axioms for mathematics, rather than a decidable, complete, and sound set of axioms.
Consistency being: it is impossible to derive a contradiction from the axioms.
Sound being: the axioms are all true
Intuitively, it seems like you want the axioms to be sound, rather than merely consistent. For example, if we have a decidable, complete, and consistent set of axioms, but one of the axioms is that $exists x exists y x + y not = y + x$, then that would not seem to be a very useful set of axioms about arithmetic. Or at least, it doesn't coincide with our intuition that addition is commutative ... we would intuitively say that that axiom is false.
So, I am trying to make sense why Hilbert was looking for a consistent set of axioms, rather than a sound set. Doing some research and thinking into this, I came up with several different explanations. I was wondering if someone could look at these and tell me if any of them actually make sense.
The axioms having some property, and knowing that the axioms have some property are two different things. So, maybe Hilbert actually was looking for a sound set of axioms, but in terms of what we would be able to prove about the axioms, he was 'merely' looking for a consistency proof. In other words, Hilbert was looking for a decidable, complete, sound, and provably consistent set of axioms (and, I assume also provably complete and provably decidable)
Hilbert was just much more concerned with consistency rather than soundness. Consistency is of course crucial: if the set is not consistent, you can derive any statement, and the whole foundation falls apart. Moreover, if you start with some 'obviously true' statements like the Peano axioms, then in order to keep the system consistent while we're adding more and more axioms, most likely the system will remain sound as well. So, as long as we make sure that things remain consistent, the set probably remains sound as well.
Hilbert (and others at the time) were concerned about the very notion of 'mathematical truth': what is it, really? For example, things are true in Euclidian geometry that are not true in non-Euclidian geometry ... and it makes little sense to insist that one of them is 'more mathematically true' than the other. So, maybe we should say that the very axioms of a system define what is true in that system ... and that there is no notion of 'truth' beyond that; we don't step outside the system, and use some other measure of truth in order to declare: "Yes, those axioms are true", or "No, actually, that one axiom is not true". Instead, to Hilbert, the axiom set being 'sound' and 'consistent' was just one and the same. Indeed, whatever can be proven from a consistent set of axioms is thereby true, so likewise 'provable' and 'true' are the same as well. (I suspect there is a link with Logical Positivism here?) In an online paper "Hilbert's Programme", C. Smorynski states (top of p.7) that Hilbert said that:
If the arbitrarily given axioms do not contradict each other with all their consequences, then they are true and the things defined by the axioms exist. This is for me the criterion of truth and existence.
(Unfortunately, Smorynski does not give the exact reference for this ... it seems like it could come from Hilbert's Grundlagen Der Geometrie ... but some translation of course ... I would love to have an exact reference for this quote .. if it is indeed a quote)
So, which of these explanations is the correct one .. if any?
logic math-history foundations philosophy
2
What do you mean by "true"? In Hilbert's program, there is NOTHING more fundamental than the "undefined terms", "definitions" and "axioms". What would you use to determine whether the axioms are "true" or not?
– user247327
2 days ago
@user247327 Good question ... not sure how I would define true, but I would say 1+1=2 is true, and 1+1=3 is not true. But I was trying to figure out what Hilbert thought ... it seems like you prefer the second explanation then?
– Bram28
2 days ago
1+ 1= 2 in a particular number system but not necessarily in others. In Hilbert's system, and, in general, in abstract mathematics, a statement is "true" if it is one of the given definitions or an axiom or can be proven from the definitions and axioms. There is NO other criterion for "true".
– user247327
2 days ago
Side point, but $1+1=3$ would cause an inconsistency in any reasonable system. False but consistent arithmetical statements are generally of the “there exists a natural number such that _” variety.
– spaceisdarkgreen
2 days ago
@spaceisdarkgreen Good point, I'll change my example ...
– Bram28
2 days ago
|
show 11 more comments
I have been wondering why exactly Hilbert asked for a decidable, complete, and consistent set of axioms for mathematics, rather than a decidable, complete, and sound set of axioms.
Consistency being: it is impossible to derive a contradiction from the axioms.
Sound being: the axioms are all true
Intuitively, it seems like you want the axioms to be sound, rather than merely consistent. For example, if we have a decidable, complete, and consistent set of axioms, but one of the axioms is that $exists x exists y x + y not = y + x$, then that would not seem to be a very useful set of axioms about arithmetic. Or at least, it doesn't coincide with our intuition that addition is commutative ... we would intuitively say that that axiom is false.
So, I am trying to make sense why Hilbert was looking for a consistent set of axioms, rather than a sound set. Doing some research and thinking into this, I came up with several different explanations. I was wondering if someone could look at these and tell me if any of them actually make sense.
The axioms having some property, and knowing that the axioms have some property are two different things. So, maybe Hilbert actually was looking for a sound set of axioms, but in terms of what we would be able to prove about the axioms, he was 'merely' looking for a consistency proof. In other words, Hilbert was looking for a decidable, complete, sound, and provably consistent set of axioms (and, I assume also provably complete and provably decidable)
Hilbert was just much more concerned with consistency rather than soundness. Consistency is of course crucial: if the set is not consistent, you can derive any statement, and the whole foundation falls apart. Moreover, if you start with some 'obviously true' statements like the Peano axioms, then in order to keep the system consistent while we're adding more and more axioms, most likely the system will remain sound as well. So, as long as we make sure that things remain consistent, the set probably remains sound as well.
Hilbert (and others at the time) were concerned about the very notion of 'mathematical truth': what is it, really? For example, things are true in Euclidian geometry that are not true in non-Euclidian geometry ... and it makes little sense to insist that one of them is 'more mathematically true' than the other. So, maybe we should say that the very axioms of a system define what is true in that system ... and that there is no notion of 'truth' beyond that; we don't step outside the system, and use some other measure of truth in order to declare: "Yes, those axioms are true", or "No, actually, that one axiom is not true". Instead, to Hilbert, the axiom set being 'sound' and 'consistent' was just one and the same. Indeed, whatever can be proven from a consistent set of axioms is thereby true, so likewise 'provable' and 'true' are the same as well. (I suspect there is a link with Logical Positivism here?) In an online paper "Hilbert's Programme", C. Smorynski states (top of p.7) that Hilbert said that:
If the arbitrarily given axioms do not contradict each other with all their consequences, then they are true and the things defined by the axioms exist. This is for me the criterion of truth and existence.
(Unfortunately, Smorynski does not give the exact reference for this ... it seems like it could come from Hilbert's Grundlagen Der Geometrie ... but some translation of course ... I would love to have an exact reference for this quote .. if it is indeed a quote)
So, which of these explanations is the correct one .. if any?
logic math-history foundations philosophy
I have been wondering why exactly Hilbert asked for a decidable, complete, and consistent set of axioms for mathematics, rather than a decidable, complete, and sound set of axioms.
Consistency being: it is impossible to derive a contradiction from the axioms.
Sound being: the axioms are all true
Intuitively, it seems like you want the axioms to be sound, rather than merely consistent. For example, if we have a decidable, complete, and consistent set of axioms, but one of the axioms is that $exists x exists y x + y not = y + x$, then that would not seem to be a very useful set of axioms about arithmetic. Or at least, it doesn't coincide with our intuition that addition is commutative ... we would intuitively say that that axiom is false.
So, I am trying to make sense why Hilbert was looking for a consistent set of axioms, rather than a sound set. Doing some research and thinking into this, I came up with several different explanations. I was wondering if someone could look at these and tell me if any of them actually make sense.
The axioms having some property, and knowing that the axioms have some property are two different things. So, maybe Hilbert actually was looking for a sound set of axioms, but in terms of what we would be able to prove about the axioms, he was 'merely' looking for a consistency proof. In other words, Hilbert was looking for a decidable, complete, sound, and provably consistent set of axioms (and, I assume also provably complete and provably decidable)
Hilbert was just much more concerned with consistency rather than soundness. Consistency is of course crucial: if the set is not consistent, you can derive any statement, and the whole foundation falls apart. Moreover, if you start with some 'obviously true' statements like the Peano axioms, then in order to keep the system consistent while we're adding more and more axioms, most likely the system will remain sound as well. So, as long as we make sure that things remain consistent, the set probably remains sound as well.
Hilbert (and others at the time) were concerned about the very notion of 'mathematical truth': what is it, really? For example, things are true in Euclidian geometry that are not true in non-Euclidian geometry ... and it makes little sense to insist that one of them is 'more mathematically true' than the other. So, maybe we should say that the very axioms of a system define what is true in that system ... and that there is no notion of 'truth' beyond that; we don't step outside the system, and use some other measure of truth in order to declare: "Yes, those axioms are true", or "No, actually, that one axiom is not true". Instead, to Hilbert, the axiom set being 'sound' and 'consistent' was just one and the same. Indeed, whatever can be proven from a consistent set of axioms is thereby true, so likewise 'provable' and 'true' are the same as well. (I suspect there is a link with Logical Positivism here?) In an online paper "Hilbert's Programme", C. Smorynski states (top of p.7) that Hilbert said that:
If the arbitrarily given axioms do not contradict each other with all their consequences, then they are true and the things defined by the axioms exist. This is for me the criterion of truth and existence.
(Unfortunately, Smorynski does not give the exact reference for this ... it seems like it could come from Hilbert's Grundlagen Der Geometrie ... but some translation of course ... I would love to have an exact reference for this quote .. if it is indeed a quote)
So, which of these explanations is the correct one .. if any?
logic math-history foundations philosophy
logic math-history foundations philosophy
edited 2 days ago
asked 2 days ago
Bram28
60.3k44590
60.3k44590
2
What do you mean by "true"? In Hilbert's program, there is NOTHING more fundamental than the "undefined terms", "definitions" and "axioms". What would you use to determine whether the axioms are "true" or not?
– user247327
2 days ago
@user247327 Good question ... not sure how I would define true, but I would say 1+1=2 is true, and 1+1=3 is not true. But I was trying to figure out what Hilbert thought ... it seems like you prefer the second explanation then?
– Bram28
2 days ago
1+ 1= 2 in a particular number system but not necessarily in others. In Hilbert's system, and, in general, in abstract mathematics, a statement is "true" if it is one of the given definitions or an axiom or can be proven from the definitions and axioms. There is NO other criterion for "true".
– user247327
2 days ago
Side point, but $1+1=3$ would cause an inconsistency in any reasonable system. False but consistent arithmetical statements are generally of the “there exists a natural number such that _” variety.
– spaceisdarkgreen
2 days ago
@spaceisdarkgreen Good point, I'll change my example ...
– Bram28
2 days ago
|
show 11 more comments
2
What do you mean by "true"? In Hilbert's program, there is NOTHING more fundamental than the "undefined terms", "definitions" and "axioms". What would you use to determine whether the axioms are "true" or not?
– user247327
2 days ago
@user247327 Good question ... not sure how I would define true, but I would say 1+1=2 is true, and 1+1=3 is not true. But I was trying to figure out what Hilbert thought ... it seems like you prefer the second explanation then?
– Bram28
2 days ago
1+ 1= 2 in a particular number system but not necessarily in others. In Hilbert's system, and, in general, in abstract mathematics, a statement is "true" if it is one of the given definitions or an axiom or can be proven from the definitions and axioms. There is NO other criterion for "true".
– user247327
2 days ago
Side point, but $1+1=3$ would cause an inconsistency in any reasonable system. False but consistent arithmetical statements are generally of the “there exists a natural number such that _” variety.
– spaceisdarkgreen
2 days ago
@spaceisdarkgreen Good point, I'll change my example ...
– Bram28
2 days ago
2
2
What do you mean by "true"? In Hilbert's program, there is NOTHING more fundamental than the "undefined terms", "definitions" and "axioms". What would you use to determine whether the axioms are "true" or not?
– user247327
2 days ago
What do you mean by "true"? In Hilbert's program, there is NOTHING more fundamental than the "undefined terms", "definitions" and "axioms". What would you use to determine whether the axioms are "true" or not?
– user247327
2 days ago
@user247327 Good question ... not sure how I would define true, but I would say 1+1=2 is true, and 1+1=3 is not true. But I was trying to figure out what Hilbert thought ... it seems like you prefer the second explanation then?
– Bram28
2 days ago
@user247327 Good question ... not sure how I would define true, but I would say 1+1=2 is true, and 1+1=3 is not true. But I was trying to figure out what Hilbert thought ... it seems like you prefer the second explanation then?
– Bram28
2 days ago
1+ 1= 2 in a particular number system but not necessarily in others. In Hilbert's system, and, in general, in abstract mathematics, a statement is "true" if it is one of the given definitions or an axiom or can be proven from the definitions and axioms. There is NO other criterion for "true".
– user247327
2 days ago
1+ 1= 2 in a particular number system but not necessarily in others. In Hilbert's system, and, in general, in abstract mathematics, a statement is "true" if it is one of the given definitions or an axiom or can be proven from the definitions and axioms. There is NO other criterion for "true".
– user247327
2 days ago
Side point, but $1+1=3$ would cause an inconsistency in any reasonable system. False but consistent arithmetical statements are generally of the “there exists a natural number such that _” variety.
– spaceisdarkgreen
2 days ago
Side point, but $1+1=3$ would cause an inconsistency in any reasonable system. False but consistent arithmetical statements are generally of the “there exists a natural number such that _” variety.
– spaceisdarkgreen
2 days ago
@spaceisdarkgreen Good point, I'll change my example ...
– Bram28
2 days ago
@spaceisdarkgreen Good point, I'll change my example ...
– Bram28
2 days ago
|
show 11 more comments
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
A likely explanation is that this is for historical reasons:
Soundness is a notion that relates provability and semantics. A logical theory $mathcal T$ is sound if whenever $varphi$ is provable in the theory, then $varphi$ is true in every $mathcal T$-structure. This is a model-theoretic notion which could only be formulated once the basic notions of model theory had been developed – and this was only done by Kurt Gödel in the early 1930s as part of his work on completeness of first-order logic.
The notion of consistency is only concerned with provability, which is all Hilbert knew. A set of sentences $Gamma$ is consistent, if $Gamma notvdash bot$, that is, we cannot prove falsehood from them.
Thanks! But maybe this just means that I misused 'sound' ... what I meant by a 'sound' axioms is that they are all true. So, to rephrase the question: why didn't Hilbert call for a decidable and complete set of axioms, all of which are true?
– Bram28
2 days ago
The idea of probability and truth as different notions is later than Hilbert.
– Hans Hüttel
2 days ago
Hmm .. that would seem to be compatible with my explanation 3 ... that is, to Hilbert: as long as we don't have any inconsistency in the axioms, then whatever I derive from the axioms is thereby true.
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3060828%2fhilbert-program-consistency-vs-soundness%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
A likely explanation is that this is for historical reasons:
Soundness is a notion that relates provability and semantics. A logical theory $mathcal T$ is sound if whenever $varphi$ is provable in the theory, then $varphi$ is true in every $mathcal T$-structure. This is a model-theoretic notion which could only be formulated once the basic notions of model theory had been developed – and this was only done by Kurt Gödel in the early 1930s as part of his work on completeness of first-order logic.
The notion of consistency is only concerned with provability, which is all Hilbert knew. A set of sentences $Gamma$ is consistent, if $Gamma notvdash bot$, that is, we cannot prove falsehood from them.
Thanks! But maybe this just means that I misused 'sound' ... what I meant by a 'sound' axioms is that they are all true. So, to rephrase the question: why didn't Hilbert call for a decidable and complete set of axioms, all of which are true?
– Bram28
2 days ago
The idea of probability and truth as different notions is later than Hilbert.
– Hans Hüttel
2 days ago
Hmm .. that would seem to be compatible with my explanation 3 ... that is, to Hilbert: as long as we don't have any inconsistency in the axioms, then whatever I derive from the axioms is thereby true.
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |
A likely explanation is that this is for historical reasons:
Soundness is a notion that relates provability and semantics. A logical theory $mathcal T$ is sound if whenever $varphi$ is provable in the theory, then $varphi$ is true in every $mathcal T$-structure. This is a model-theoretic notion which could only be formulated once the basic notions of model theory had been developed – and this was only done by Kurt Gödel in the early 1930s as part of his work on completeness of first-order logic.
The notion of consistency is only concerned with provability, which is all Hilbert knew. A set of sentences $Gamma$ is consistent, if $Gamma notvdash bot$, that is, we cannot prove falsehood from them.
Thanks! But maybe this just means that I misused 'sound' ... what I meant by a 'sound' axioms is that they are all true. So, to rephrase the question: why didn't Hilbert call for a decidable and complete set of axioms, all of which are true?
– Bram28
2 days ago
The idea of probability and truth as different notions is later than Hilbert.
– Hans Hüttel
2 days ago
Hmm .. that would seem to be compatible with my explanation 3 ... that is, to Hilbert: as long as we don't have any inconsistency in the axioms, then whatever I derive from the axioms is thereby true.
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |
A likely explanation is that this is for historical reasons:
Soundness is a notion that relates provability and semantics. A logical theory $mathcal T$ is sound if whenever $varphi$ is provable in the theory, then $varphi$ is true in every $mathcal T$-structure. This is a model-theoretic notion which could only be formulated once the basic notions of model theory had been developed – and this was only done by Kurt Gödel in the early 1930s as part of his work on completeness of first-order logic.
The notion of consistency is only concerned with provability, which is all Hilbert knew. A set of sentences $Gamma$ is consistent, if $Gamma notvdash bot$, that is, we cannot prove falsehood from them.
A likely explanation is that this is for historical reasons:
Soundness is a notion that relates provability and semantics. A logical theory $mathcal T$ is sound if whenever $varphi$ is provable in the theory, then $varphi$ is true in every $mathcal T$-structure. This is a model-theoretic notion which could only be formulated once the basic notions of model theory had been developed – and this was only done by Kurt Gödel in the early 1930s as part of his work on completeness of first-order logic.
The notion of consistency is only concerned with provability, which is all Hilbert knew. A set of sentences $Gamma$ is consistent, if $Gamma notvdash bot$, that is, we cannot prove falsehood from them.
answered 2 days ago
Hans Hüttel
3,1972921
3,1972921
Thanks! But maybe this just means that I misused 'sound' ... what I meant by a 'sound' axioms is that they are all true. So, to rephrase the question: why didn't Hilbert call for a decidable and complete set of axioms, all of which are true?
– Bram28
2 days ago
The idea of probability and truth as different notions is later than Hilbert.
– Hans Hüttel
2 days ago
Hmm .. that would seem to be compatible with my explanation 3 ... that is, to Hilbert: as long as we don't have any inconsistency in the axioms, then whatever I derive from the axioms is thereby true.
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |
Thanks! But maybe this just means that I misused 'sound' ... what I meant by a 'sound' axioms is that they are all true. So, to rephrase the question: why didn't Hilbert call for a decidable and complete set of axioms, all of which are true?
– Bram28
2 days ago
The idea of probability and truth as different notions is later than Hilbert.
– Hans Hüttel
2 days ago
Hmm .. that would seem to be compatible with my explanation 3 ... that is, to Hilbert: as long as we don't have any inconsistency in the axioms, then whatever I derive from the axioms is thereby true.
– Bram28
2 days ago
Thanks! But maybe this just means that I misused 'sound' ... what I meant by a 'sound' axioms is that they are all true. So, to rephrase the question: why didn't Hilbert call for a decidable and complete set of axioms, all of which are true?
– Bram28
2 days ago
Thanks! But maybe this just means that I misused 'sound' ... what I meant by a 'sound' axioms is that they are all true. So, to rephrase the question: why didn't Hilbert call for a decidable and complete set of axioms, all of which are true?
– Bram28
2 days ago
The idea of probability and truth as different notions is later than Hilbert.
– Hans Hüttel
2 days ago
The idea of probability and truth as different notions is later than Hilbert.
– Hans Hüttel
2 days ago
Hmm .. that would seem to be compatible with my explanation 3 ... that is, to Hilbert: as long as we don't have any inconsistency in the axioms, then whatever I derive from the axioms is thereby true.
– Bram28
2 days ago
Hmm .. that would seem to be compatible with my explanation 3 ... that is, to Hilbert: as long as we don't have any inconsistency in the axioms, then whatever I derive from the axioms is thereby true.
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.
Please pay close attention to the following guidance:
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3060828%2fhilbert-program-consistency-vs-soundness%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
2
What do you mean by "true"? In Hilbert's program, there is NOTHING more fundamental than the "undefined terms", "definitions" and "axioms". What would you use to determine whether the axioms are "true" or not?
– user247327
2 days ago
@user247327 Good question ... not sure how I would define true, but I would say 1+1=2 is true, and 1+1=3 is not true. But I was trying to figure out what Hilbert thought ... it seems like you prefer the second explanation then?
– Bram28
2 days ago
1+ 1= 2 in a particular number system but not necessarily in others. In Hilbert's system, and, in general, in abstract mathematics, a statement is "true" if it is one of the given definitions or an axiom or can be proven from the definitions and axioms. There is NO other criterion for "true".
– user247327
2 days ago
Side point, but $1+1=3$ would cause an inconsistency in any reasonable system. False but consistent arithmetical statements are generally of the “there exists a natural number such that _” variety.
– spaceisdarkgreen
2 days ago
@spaceisdarkgreen Good point, I'll change my example ...
– Bram28
2 days ago