Proof in EGA I Chapter 0, point 3.2.2
I am reading the proof of a necessary and sufficient condition for a presheaf over a base of a topology to be a sheaf, from Élements de Géometrie Algébrique I, chapter 0, point 3.2.2. There is a line where I'm lost and I can't understand where the things the author says come from.
Context
Let $X$ be a topological space and $B$ a base of its topology, considered as a category with inclusion maps as morphisms. A presheaf on $B$ is just a contravariant functor $mathcal{F}:Bto mathcal{C}$, where $mathcal{C}$ is any category that admits projective limits. Denote by $rho^U_V:mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ the restriction morphisms. From this we can define a presheaf $mathcal{F}'$ on $X$ by setting $mathcal{F}'(U)=varprojlimmathcal{F}(V)$, where $Vsubseteq U$ and $Vin B$.
In the proof of 0-3.2.2, the author bassicaly shows that this definition doesn't depend on $B$ and therefore it fulfills the condition needed to be a sheaf with the following hypothesis:
For every covering $(U_alpha)$ of $Uin B$ by sets $U_alphain B$ contained in $U$, and for every object $Tinmathcal{C}$, the map that sends every $finmathrm{Hom}(T,mathcal{F}(U))$ to the family $(rho^U_{U_alpha}circ f)inprodmathrm{Hom}(T,mathcal{F}(U_alpha))$ is a bijection onto the the family $(f_alpha)$ such that $rho^{U_alpha}_Vcirc f_alpha=rho^{U_beta}_Vcirc f_beta$ for every pair of indices $(alpha,beta)$ and every $Vin B$ with $Vsubseteq U_alphacap U_beta$.
In order to do that, he chooses a base $B'subseteq B$, and defines $mathcal{F}''$ in the same way as $mathcal{F}'$ but taking projective limit over the elements of $B'$.
Question
For every open set $U$ there is a morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ which is the projective limit of $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ for $Vin B'$. Now, if $Uin B$, we want to show that $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ is an isomorphism, and the following is stated
il est immédiat de voir que les composés des morphismes $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ et $mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}(U)$ ainsi définis sont les identités.
In english:
it is immediate to see that the compositions of the morphisms $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}(U)$ defined like this are identities.
What I don't see is how is $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ defined. The other direction is straight forward from the universal property of the projective limit, but there is no clue in the previous text of how $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ is defined (or at least I can't find it).
Alternative
Alternatively, I tried to prove the theorem using the morphisms $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, given by the filtering property of any base. But I don't know how to show that these compositions are identities. I would consider my question answered if this alternative is answered.
algebraic-geometry proof-explanation sheaf-theory
add a comment |
I am reading the proof of a necessary and sufficient condition for a presheaf over a base of a topology to be a sheaf, from Élements de Géometrie Algébrique I, chapter 0, point 3.2.2. There is a line where I'm lost and I can't understand where the things the author says come from.
Context
Let $X$ be a topological space and $B$ a base of its topology, considered as a category with inclusion maps as morphisms. A presheaf on $B$ is just a contravariant functor $mathcal{F}:Bto mathcal{C}$, where $mathcal{C}$ is any category that admits projective limits. Denote by $rho^U_V:mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ the restriction morphisms. From this we can define a presheaf $mathcal{F}'$ on $X$ by setting $mathcal{F}'(U)=varprojlimmathcal{F}(V)$, where $Vsubseteq U$ and $Vin B$.
In the proof of 0-3.2.2, the author bassicaly shows that this definition doesn't depend on $B$ and therefore it fulfills the condition needed to be a sheaf with the following hypothesis:
For every covering $(U_alpha)$ of $Uin B$ by sets $U_alphain B$ contained in $U$, and for every object $Tinmathcal{C}$, the map that sends every $finmathrm{Hom}(T,mathcal{F}(U))$ to the family $(rho^U_{U_alpha}circ f)inprodmathrm{Hom}(T,mathcal{F}(U_alpha))$ is a bijection onto the the family $(f_alpha)$ such that $rho^{U_alpha}_Vcirc f_alpha=rho^{U_beta}_Vcirc f_beta$ for every pair of indices $(alpha,beta)$ and every $Vin B$ with $Vsubseteq U_alphacap U_beta$.
In order to do that, he chooses a base $B'subseteq B$, and defines $mathcal{F}''$ in the same way as $mathcal{F}'$ but taking projective limit over the elements of $B'$.
Question
For every open set $U$ there is a morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ which is the projective limit of $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ for $Vin B'$. Now, if $Uin B$, we want to show that $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ is an isomorphism, and the following is stated
il est immédiat de voir que les composés des morphismes $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ et $mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}(U)$ ainsi définis sont les identités.
In english:
it is immediate to see that the compositions of the morphisms $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}(U)$ defined like this are identities.
What I don't see is how is $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ defined. The other direction is straight forward from the universal property of the projective limit, but there is no clue in the previous text of how $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ is defined (or at least I can't find it).
Alternative
Alternatively, I tried to prove the theorem using the morphisms $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, given by the filtering property of any base. But I don't know how to show that these compositions are identities. I would consider my question answered if this alternative is answered.
algebraic-geometry proof-explanation sheaf-theory
4
Please include the definitions of $mathcal{F}$ and $mathcal{F}''$ in the question. Not everyone has a copy of EGA close to hand.
– Alex Kruckman
2 days ago
1
I'm doing it, I just wanted to first post the question for those who had a copy to be able to answer and in the meantime I'm editing the question to define them @AlexKruckman .
– Javi
2 days ago
1
Do we really deal with $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and an opposite arrow, or we have the morphisms $mathcal{F}^{color{red}{prime}}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, which do the job, because of the "filtering property" of any base... (?!)
– dan_fulea
2 days ago
@dan_fulea actually I'm not sure. I tried to prove the theorem using the morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, but I don't know how to show that the compositions are identities in that case.
– Javi
2 days ago
add a comment |
I am reading the proof of a necessary and sufficient condition for a presheaf over a base of a topology to be a sheaf, from Élements de Géometrie Algébrique I, chapter 0, point 3.2.2. There is a line where I'm lost and I can't understand where the things the author says come from.
Context
Let $X$ be a topological space and $B$ a base of its topology, considered as a category with inclusion maps as morphisms. A presheaf on $B$ is just a contravariant functor $mathcal{F}:Bto mathcal{C}$, where $mathcal{C}$ is any category that admits projective limits. Denote by $rho^U_V:mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ the restriction morphisms. From this we can define a presheaf $mathcal{F}'$ on $X$ by setting $mathcal{F}'(U)=varprojlimmathcal{F}(V)$, where $Vsubseteq U$ and $Vin B$.
In the proof of 0-3.2.2, the author bassicaly shows that this definition doesn't depend on $B$ and therefore it fulfills the condition needed to be a sheaf with the following hypothesis:
For every covering $(U_alpha)$ of $Uin B$ by sets $U_alphain B$ contained in $U$, and for every object $Tinmathcal{C}$, the map that sends every $finmathrm{Hom}(T,mathcal{F}(U))$ to the family $(rho^U_{U_alpha}circ f)inprodmathrm{Hom}(T,mathcal{F}(U_alpha))$ is a bijection onto the the family $(f_alpha)$ such that $rho^{U_alpha}_Vcirc f_alpha=rho^{U_beta}_Vcirc f_beta$ for every pair of indices $(alpha,beta)$ and every $Vin B$ with $Vsubseteq U_alphacap U_beta$.
In order to do that, he chooses a base $B'subseteq B$, and defines $mathcal{F}''$ in the same way as $mathcal{F}'$ but taking projective limit over the elements of $B'$.
Question
For every open set $U$ there is a morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ which is the projective limit of $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ for $Vin B'$. Now, if $Uin B$, we want to show that $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ is an isomorphism, and the following is stated
il est immédiat de voir que les composés des morphismes $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ et $mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}(U)$ ainsi définis sont les identités.
In english:
it is immediate to see that the compositions of the morphisms $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}(U)$ defined like this are identities.
What I don't see is how is $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ defined. The other direction is straight forward from the universal property of the projective limit, but there is no clue in the previous text of how $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ is defined (or at least I can't find it).
Alternative
Alternatively, I tried to prove the theorem using the morphisms $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, given by the filtering property of any base. But I don't know how to show that these compositions are identities. I would consider my question answered if this alternative is answered.
algebraic-geometry proof-explanation sheaf-theory
I am reading the proof of a necessary and sufficient condition for a presheaf over a base of a topology to be a sheaf, from Élements de Géometrie Algébrique I, chapter 0, point 3.2.2. There is a line where I'm lost and I can't understand where the things the author says come from.
Context
Let $X$ be a topological space and $B$ a base of its topology, considered as a category with inclusion maps as morphisms. A presheaf on $B$ is just a contravariant functor $mathcal{F}:Bto mathcal{C}$, where $mathcal{C}$ is any category that admits projective limits. Denote by $rho^U_V:mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ the restriction morphisms. From this we can define a presheaf $mathcal{F}'$ on $X$ by setting $mathcal{F}'(U)=varprojlimmathcal{F}(V)$, where $Vsubseteq U$ and $Vin B$.
In the proof of 0-3.2.2, the author bassicaly shows that this definition doesn't depend on $B$ and therefore it fulfills the condition needed to be a sheaf with the following hypothesis:
For every covering $(U_alpha)$ of $Uin B$ by sets $U_alphain B$ contained in $U$, and for every object $Tinmathcal{C}$, the map that sends every $finmathrm{Hom}(T,mathcal{F}(U))$ to the family $(rho^U_{U_alpha}circ f)inprodmathrm{Hom}(T,mathcal{F}(U_alpha))$ is a bijection onto the the family $(f_alpha)$ such that $rho^{U_alpha}_Vcirc f_alpha=rho^{U_beta}_Vcirc f_beta$ for every pair of indices $(alpha,beta)$ and every $Vin B$ with $Vsubseteq U_alphacap U_beta$.
In order to do that, he chooses a base $B'subseteq B$, and defines $mathcal{F}''$ in the same way as $mathcal{F}'$ but taking projective limit over the elements of $B'$.
Question
For every open set $U$ there is a morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ which is the projective limit of $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ for $Vin B'$. Now, if $Uin B$, we want to show that $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ is an isomorphism, and the following is stated
il est immédiat de voir que les composés des morphismes $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ et $mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}(U)$ ainsi définis sont les identités.
In english:
it is immediate to see that the compositions of the morphisms $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}(U)$ defined like this are identities.
What I don't see is how is $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ defined. The other direction is straight forward from the universal property of the projective limit, but there is no clue in the previous text of how $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ is defined (or at least I can't find it).
Alternative
Alternatively, I tried to prove the theorem using the morphisms $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, given by the filtering property of any base. But I don't know how to show that these compositions are identities. I would consider my question answered if this alternative is answered.
algebraic-geometry proof-explanation sheaf-theory
algebraic-geometry proof-explanation sheaf-theory
edited yesterday
André 3000
12.5k22042
12.5k22042
asked 2 days ago
Javi
2,5822826
2,5822826
4
Please include the definitions of $mathcal{F}$ and $mathcal{F}''$ in the question. Not everyone has a copy of EGA close to hand.
– Alex Kruckman
2 days ago
1
I'm doing it, I just wanted to first post the question for those who had a copy to be able to answer and in the meantime I'm editing the question to define them @AlexKruckman .
– Javi
2 days ago
1
Do we really deal with $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and an opposite arrow, or we have the morphisms $mathcal{F}^{color{red}{prime}}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, which do the job, because of the "filtering property" of any base... (?!)
– dan_fulea
2 days ago
@dan_fulea actually I'm not sure. I tried to prove the theorem using the morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, but I don't know how to show that the compositions are identities in that case.
– Javi
2 days ago
add a comment |
4
Please include the definitions of $mathcal{F}$ and $mathcal{F}''$ in the question. Not everyone has a copy of EGA close to hand.
– Alex Kruckman
2 days ago
1
I'm doing it, I just wanted to first post the question for those who had a copy to be able to answer and in the meantime I'm editing the question to define them @AlexKruckman .
– Javi
2 days ago
1
Do we really deal with $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and an opposite arrow, or we have the morphisms $mathcal{F}^{color{red}{prime}}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, which do the job, because of the "filtering property" of any base... (?!)
– dan_fulea
2 days ago
@dan_fulea actually I'm not sure. I tried to prove the theorem using the morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, but I don't know how to show that the compositions are identities in that case.
– Javi
2 days ago
4
4
Please include the definitions of $mathcal{F}$ and $mathcal{F}''$ in the question. Not everyone has a copy of EGA close to hand.
– Alex Kruckman
2 days ago
Please include the definitions of $mathcal{F}$ and $mathcal{F}''$ in the question. Not everyone has a copy of EGA close to hand.
– Alex Kruckman
2 days ago
1
1
I'm doing it, I just wanted to first post the question for those who had a copy to be able to answer and in the meantime I'm editing the question to define them @AlexKruckman .
– Javi
2 days ago
I'm doing it, I just wanted to first post the question for those who had a copy to be able to answer and in the meantime I'm editing the question to define them @AlexKruckman .
– Javi
2 days ago
1
1
Do we really deal with $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and an opposite arrow, or we have the morphisms $mathcal{F}^{color{red}{prime}}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, which do the job, because of the "filtering property" of any base... (?!)
– dan_fulea
2 days ago
Do we really deal with $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and an opposite arrow, or we have the morphisms $mathcal{F}^{color{red}{prime}}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, which do the job, because of the "filtering property" of any base... (?!)
– dan_fulea
2 days ago
@dan_fulea actually I'm not sure. I tried to prove the theorem using the morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, but I don't know how to show that the compositions are identities in that case.
– Javi
2 days ago
@dan_fulea actually I'm not sure. I tried to prove the theorem using the morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, but I don't know how to show that the compositions are identities in that case.
– Javi
2 days ago
add a comment |
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
I found a way to prove the statement using the alternative idea.
Let's call $f:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $g:mathcal{F}''(U)to mathcal{F}'(U)$. Then, by commutativity we can decompose $rho_{UV}:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ as $mathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}(V)$, which is $fgcircrho_{UV}$. Therefore we have $rho_{UV}circ id_V=fgcircrho_{UV}$ for every $V$. Using the hypothesis, $fg$ must be the identity, and therefore we have the isomorphism.
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3060832%2fproof-in-ega-i-chapter-0-point-3-2-2%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
I found a way to prove the statement using the alternative idea.
Let's call $f:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $g:mathcal{F}''(U)to mathcal{F}'(U)$. Then, by commutativity we can decompose $rho_{UV}:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ as $mathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}(V)$, which is $fgcircrho_{UV}$. Therefore we have $rho_{UV}circ id_V=fgcircrho_{UV}$ for every $V$. Using the hypothesis, $fg$ must be the identity, and therefore we have the isomorphism.
add a comment |
I found a way to prove the statement using the alternative idea.
Let's call $f:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $g:mathcal{F}''(U)to mathcal{F}'(U)$. Then, by commutativity we can decompose $rho_{UV}:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ as $mathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}(V)$, which is $fgcircrho_{UV}$. Therefore we have $rho_{UV}circ id_V=fgcircrho_{UV}$ for every $V$. Using the hypothesis, $fg$ must be the identity, and therefore we have the isomorphism.
add a comment |
I found a way to prove the statement using the alternative idea.
Let's call $f:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $g:mathcal{F}''(U)to mathcal{F}'(U)$. Then, by commutativity we can decompose $rho_{UV}:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ as $mathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}(V)$, which is $fgcircrho_{UV}$. Therefore we have $rho_{UV}circ id_V=fgcircrho_{UV}$ for every $V$. Using the hypothesis, $fg$ must be the identity, and therefore we have the isomorphism.
I found a way to prove the statement using the alternative idea.
Let's call $f:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and $g:mathcal{F}''(U)to mathcal{F}'(U)$. Then, by commutativity we can decompose $rho_{UV}:mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}(V)$ as $mathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}''(U)tomathcal{F}'(U)to mathcal{F}(V)$, which is $fgcircrho_{UV}$. Therefore we have $rho_{UV}circ id_V=fgcircrho_{UV}$ for every $V$. Using the hypothesis, $fg$ must be the identity, and therefore we have the isomorphism.
answered yesterday
Javi
2,5822826
2,5822826
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.
Please pay close attention to the following guidance:
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3060832%2fproof-in-ega-i-chapter-0-point-3-2-2%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
4
Please include the definitions of $mathcal{F}$ and $mathcal{F}''$ in the question. Not everyone has a copy of EGA close to hand.
– Alex Kruckman
2 days ago
1
I'm doing it, I just wanted to first post the question for those who had a copy to be able to answer and in the meantime I'm editing the question to define them @AlexKruckman .
– Javi
2 days ago
1
Do we really deal with $mathcal{F}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and an opposite arrow, or we have the morphisms $mathcal{F}^{color{red}{prime}}(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, which do the job, because of the "filtering property" of any base... (?!)
– dan_fulea
2 days ago
@dan_fulea actually I'm not sure. I tried to prove the theorem using the morphism $mathcal{F}'(U)tomathcal{F}''(U)$ and back, but I don't know how to show that the compositions are identities in that case.
– Javi
2 days ago