Finite chain condition - Variation of Martin's Axiom statement
In the following $k$ and $w$ will be cardinal numbers.
Consider the classical statement $MA(k)$:
For any partial order $P$ satisfying the countable chain condition (hereafter $ccc$) and any family $D$ of dense sets in $P$ such that $|D| = k$, there is a filter $F$ on $P$ such that $F cap d$ is non-empty for every $d$ in $D$
Let's generalize it to the statement $MA(w, k)$ that replaces the $ccc$ by any width $w$, stating:
For any partial order $P$ satisfying that every strong antichain is of cardinality $less$ than $w$ [...etc]
Eg. $MA(aleph_1, k) = MA(k)$
Of course, $MA(w, k)$ implies $MA(w', k')$ for every $w' geq w$ and $k' geq k$
Now, I was wondering why $MA$ was so specific about antichains being countable, so to motivate the classical definition I tried mapping $MA$'s validity for each $w$ and $k$ pair. So far I've got:
$MA(w, k)$ is true for all $k leq aleph_0$
$MA(aleph_1, 2^{aleph_0}) = MA(2^{aleph_0})$ is false, and then so it is for any $w$ and $k$ equal or greater
$MA(aleph_1, k) = MA(k)$ is independent from but consistent with $ZFC$ for every $aleph_1 leq k < 2^{aleph_0}$
$MA(aleph_2, aleph_1)$ is false, and then so it is for any $w$ and $k$ equal or greater
So $MA$ is no use stated for longer than countable antichains. But the case I can't figure out is for $w = aleph_0$ and $k > aleph_0$.
So the question is: Why $ccc$? What can be said about the validity of $MA$ when stated for posets sastisfying that every strong antichain is finite but given an uncountable number of dense sets? Does a filter always or never exist? Is it equivalent to the case $w = aleph_1$ (ie. is allowing arbitrarily long but finite antichains equivalent to allowing countable ones too)?
set-theory first-order-logic order-theory cardinals forcing
|
show 19 more comments
In the following $k$ and $w$ will be cardinal numbers.
Consider the classical statement $MA(k)$:
For any partial order $P$ satisfying the countable chain condition (hereafter $ccc$) and any family $D$ of dense sets in $P$ such that $|D| = k$, there is a filter $F$ on $P$ such that $F cap d$ is non-empty for every $d$ in $D$
Let's generalize it to the statement $MA(w, k)$ that replaces the $ccc$ by any width $w$, stating:
For any partial order $P$ satisfying that every strong antichain is of cardinality $less$ than $w$ [...etc]
Eg. $MA(aleph_1, k) = MA(k)$
Of course, $MA(w, k)$ implies $MA(w', k')$ for every $w' geq w$ and $k' geq k$
Now, I was wondering why $MA$ was so specific about antichains being countable, so to motivate the classical definition I tried mapping $MA$'s validity for each $w$ and $k$ pair. So far I've got:
$MA(w, k)$ is true for all $k leq aleph_0$
$MA(aleph_1, 2^{aleph_0}) = MA(2^{aleph_0})$ is false, and then so it is for any $w$ and $k$ equal or greater
$MA(aleph_1, k) = MA(k)$ is independent from but consistent with $ZFC$ for every $aleph_1 leq k < 2^{aleph_0}$
$MA(aleph_2, aleph_1)$ is false, and then so it is for any $w$ and $k$ equal or greater
So $MA$ is no use stated for longer than countable antichains. But the case I can't figure out is for $w = aleph_0$ and $k > aleph_0$.
So the question is: Why $ccc$? What can be said about the validity of $MA$ when stated for posets sastisfying that every strong antichain is finite but given an uncountable number of dense sets? Does a filter always or never exist? Is it equivalent to the case $w = aleph_1$ (ie. is allowing arbitrarily long but finite antichains equivalent to allowing countable ones too)?
set-theory first-order-logic order-theory cardinals forcing
You're missing/ignoring the requirement that the forcing notions must be separative.
– Not Mike
2 days ago
1
@NotMike I'm very new to this, and I don't understand why is that required in any sense for any of my statements/questions
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
2
Replacing "ccc" by uncountable cardinals is a very difficult problem. Recently James Cummings, Mirna Dzamonja, and Itay Neeman have proposed a nice generalization. You can find it on arXiv. Other than this, you'd venture well into generalized properness, which is depressingly convoluted and hard to understand, main works are by Shelah and Roslanowski.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
2
I mean that there are a lot inherent difficulties in forcing axioms which do not revolve around $omega$ in some significant way.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
1
The point is not to "just change ccc", but also to get something which is consistent and helpful in proving similar consequences to what MA provides us with.
– Asaf Karagila♦
5 hours ago
|
show 19 more comments
In the following $k$ and $w$ will be cardinal numbers.
Consider the classical statement $MA(k)$:
For any partial order $P$ satisfying the countable chain condition (hereafter $ccc$) and any family $D$ of dense sets in $P$ such that $|D| = k$, there is a filter $F$ on $P$ such that $F cap d$ is non-empty for every $d$ in $D$
Let's generalize it to the statement $MA(w, k)$ that replaces the $ccc$ by any width $w$, stating:
For any partial order $P$ satisfying that every strong antichain is of cardinality $less$ than $w$ [...etc]
Eg. $MA(aleph_1, k) = MA(k)$
Of course, $MA(w, k)$ implies $MA(w', k')$ for every $w' geq w$ and $k' geq k$
Now, I was wondering why $MA$ was so specific about antichains being countable, so to motivate the classical definition I tried mapping $MA$'s validity for each $w$ and $k$ pair. So far I've got:
$MA(w, k)$ is true for all $k leq aleph_0$
$MA(aleph_1, 2^{aleph_0}) = MA(2^{aleph_0})$ is false, and then so it is for any $w$ and $k$ equal or greater
$MA(aleph_1, k) = MA(k)$ is independent from but consistent with $ZFC$ for every $aleph_1 leq k < 2^{aleph_0}$
$MA(aleph_2, aleph_1)$ is false, and then so it is for any $w$ and $k$ equal or greater
So $MA$ is no use stated for longer than countable antichains. But the case I can't figure out is for $w = aleph_0$ and $k > aleph_0$.
So the question is: Why $ccc$? What can be said about the validity of $MA$ when stated for posets sastisfying that every strong antichain is finite but given an uncountable number of dense sets? Does a filter always or never exist? Is it equivalent to the case $w = aleph_1$ (ie. is allowing arbitrarily long but finite antichains equivalent to allowing countable ones too)?
set-theory first-order-logic order-theory cardinals forcing
In the following $k$ and $w$ will be cardinal numbers.
Consider the classical statement $MA(k)$:
For any partial order $P$ satisfying the countable chain condition (hereafter $ccc$) and any family $D$ of dense sets in $P$ such that $|D| = k$, there is a filter $F$ on $P$ such that $F cap d$ is non-empty for every $d$ in $D$
Let's generalize it to the statement $MA(w, k)$ that replaces the $ccc$ by any width $w$, stating:
For any partial order $P$ satisfying that every strong antichain is of cardinality $less$ than $w$ [...etc]
Eg. $MA(aleph_1, k) = MA(k)$
Of course, $MA(w, k)$ implies $MA(w', k')$ for every $w' geq w$ and $k' geq k$
Now, I was wondering why $MA$ was so specific about antichains being countable, so to motivate the classical definition I tried mapping $MA$'s validity for each $w$ and $k$ pair. So far I've got:
$MA(w, k)$ is true for all $k leq aleph_0$
$MA(aleph_1, 2^{aleph_0}) = MA(2^{aleph_0})$ is false, and then so it is for any $w$ and $k$ equal or greater
$MA(aleph_1, k) = MA(k)$ is independent from but consistent with $ZFC$ for every $aleph_1 leq k < 2^{aleph_0}$
$MA(aleph_2, aleph_1)$ is false, and then so it is for any $w$ and $k$ equal or greater
So $MA$ is no use stated for longer than countable antichains. But the case I can't figure out is for $w = aleph_0$ and $k > aleph_0$.
So the question is: Why $ccc$? What can be said about the validity of $MA$ when stated for posets sastisfying that every strong antichain is finite but given an uncountable number of dense sets? Does a filter always or never exist? Is it equivalent to the case $w = aleph_1$ (ie. is allowing arbitrarily long but finite antichains equivalent to allowing countable ones too)?
set-theory first-order-logic order-theory cardinals forcing
set-theory first-order-logic order-theory cardinals forcing
edited 6 hours ago
asked 2 days ago
Emilio Martinez
1246
1246
You're missing/ignoring the requirement that the forcing notions must be separative.
– Not Mike
2 days ago
1
@NotMike I'm very new to this, and I don't understand why is that required in any sense for any of my statements/questions
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
2
Replacing "ccc" by uncountable cardinals is a very difficult problem. Recently James Cummings, Mirna Dzamonja, and Itay Neeman have proposed a nice generalization. You can find it on arXiv. Other than this, you'd venture well into generalized properness, which is depressingly convoluted and hard to understand, main works are by Shelah and Roslanowski.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
2
I mean that there are a lot inherent difficulties in forcing axioms which do not revolve around $omega$ in some significant way.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
1
The point is not to "just change ccc", but also to get something which is consistent and helpful in proving similar consequences to what MA provides us with.
– Asaf Karagila♦
5 hours ago
|
show 19 more comments
You're missing/ignoring the requirement that the forcing notions must be separative.
– Not Mike
2 days ago
1
@NotMike I'm very new to this, and I don't understand why is that required in any sense for any of my statements/questions
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
2
Replacing "ccc" by uncountable cardinals is a very difficult problem. Recently James Cummings, Mirna Dzamonja, and Itay Neeman have proposed a nice generalization. You can find it on arXiv. Other than this, you'd venture well into generalized properness, which is depressingly convoluted and hard to understand, main works are by Shelah and Roslanowski.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
2
I mean that there are a lot inherent difficulties in forcing axioms which do not revolve around $omega$ in some significant way.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
1
The point is not to "just change ccc", but also to get something which is consistent and helpful in proving similar consequences to what MA provides us with.
– Asaf Karagila♦
5 hours ago
You're missing/ignoring the requirement that the forcing notions must be separative.
– Not Mike
2 days ago
You're missing/ignoring the requirement that the forcing notions must be separative.
– Not Mike
2 days ago
1
1
@NotMike I'm very new to this, and I don't understand why is that required in any sense for any of my statements/questions
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
@NotMike I'm very new to this, and I don't understand why is that required in any sense for any of my statements/questions
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
2
2
Replacing "ccc" by uncountable cardinals is a very difficult problem. Recently James Cummings, Mirna Dzamonja, and Itay Neeman have proposed a nice generalization. You can find it on arXiv. Other than this, you'd venture well into generalized properness, which is depressingly convoluted and hard to understand, main works are by Shelah and Roslanowski.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
Replacing "ccc" by uncountable cardinals is a very difficult problem. Recently James Cummings, Mirna Dzamonja, and Itay Neeman have proposed a nice generalization. You can find it on arXiv. Other than this, you'd venture well into generalized properness, which is depressingly convoluted and hard to understand, main works are by Shelah and Roslanowski.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
2
2
I mean that there are a lot inherent difficulties in forcing axioms which do not revolve around $omega$ in some significant way.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
I mean that there are a lot inherent difficulties in forcing axioms which do not revolve around $omega$ in some significant way.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
1
1
The point is not to "just change ccc", but also to get something which is consistent and helpful in proving similar consequences to what MA provides us with.
– Asaf Karagila♦
5 hours ago
The point is not to "just change ccc", but also to get something which is consistent and helpful in proving similar consequences to what MA provides us with.
– Asaf Karagila♦
5 hours ago
|
show 19 more comments
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
The issue is that a poset where all strong antichains have finite width is trivial - at least, as far as forcing is concerned - and so the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom is trivial too.
To see that such forcings are trivial, the key point is the following:
Let $mathbb{P}$ be a poset with an element $p$ such that every $q_1,q_2le p$ have a common extension $r$ (that is, $p$ doesn't bound any nontrivial strong antichain). Then there is a $mathbb{P}$-generic filter in the ground model already.
The proof is simple: let $G$ be the set of all conditions compatible with $p$.
Now suppose $mathbb{P}$ is a poset where every strong antichain is finite. I claim that $mathbb{P}$ has such a "trivializing" element $p$. For if not, we can inductively define a map $t$ from $2^{<omega}$ to $mathbb{P}$ such that:
$sigmaprectauimplies t(sigma)ge t(tau)$.
$t(sigma0)perp t(sigma1)$.
But then the set $${t(0), t(10), t(110), t(1110), ...}$$ forms an infinite strong antichain in $mathbb{P}$.
In fact, we can do even better (since having only finite strong antichains is preserved by passing from $mathbb{P}$ to $mathbb{P}_{le s}$):
If $mathbb{P}$ has only finite strong antichains, then the set of "trivializing" $p$ is dense in $mathbb{P}$; so every $mathbb{P}$-generic filter is already in the ground model. (And consequently, we have "${bf MA(aleph_0,infty)}$.")
So such a poset really is trivial (in the sense of forcing), not just "possibly trivial," as is the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom.
Thanks. It was my intuition that the problem would trivilize like that, but I hadn't yet matured the subject enough to prove it.
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3060799%2ffinite-chain-condition-variation-of-martins-axiom-statement%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
The issue is that a poset where all strong antichains have finite width is trivial - at least, as far as forcing is concerned - and so the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom is trivial too.
To see that such forcings are trivial, the key point is the following:
Let $mathbb{P}$ be a poset with an element $p$ such that every $q_1,q_2le p$ have a common extension $r$ (that is, $p$ doesn't bound any nontrivial strong antichain). Then there is a $mathbb{P}$-generic filter in the ground model already.
The proof is simple: let $G$ be the set of all conditions compatible with $p$.
Now suppose $mathbb{P}$ is a poset where every strong antichain is finite. I claim that $mathbb{P}$ has such a "trivializing" element $p$. For if not, we can inductively define a map $t$ from $2^{<omega}$ to $mathbb{P}$ such that:
$sigmaprectauimplies t(sigma)ge t(tau)$.
$t(sigma0)perp t(sigma1)$.
But then the set $${t(0), t(10), t(110), t(1110), ...}$$ forms an infinite strong antichain in $mathbb{P}$.
In fact, we can do even better (since having only finite strong antichains is preserved by passing from $mathbb{P}$ to $mathbb{P}_{le s}$):
If $mathbb{P}$ has only finite strong antichains, then the set of "trivializing" $p$ is dense in $mathbb{P}$; so every $mathbb{P}$-generic filter is already in the ground model. (And consequently, we have "${bf MA(aleph_0,infty)}$.")
So such a poset really is trivial (in the sense of forcing), not just "possibly trivial," as is the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom.
Thanks. It was my intuition that the problem would trivilize like that, but I hadn't yet matured the subject enough to prove it.
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
add a comment |
The issue is that a poset where all strong antichains have finite width is trivial - at least, as far as forcing is concerned - and so the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom is trivial too.
To see that such forcings are trivial, the key point is the following:
Let $mathbb{P}$ be a poset with an element $p$ such that every $q_1,q_2le p$ have a common extension $r$ (that is, $p$ doesn't bound any nontrivial strong antichain). Then there is a $mathbb{P}$-generic filter in the ground model already.
The proof is simple: let $G$ be the set of all conditions compatible with $p$.
Now suppose $mathbb{P}$ is a poset where every strong antichain is finite. I claim that $mathbb{P}$ has such a "trivializing" element $p$. For if not, we can inductively define a map $t$ from $2^{<omega}$ to $mathbb{P}$ such that:
$sigmaprectauimplies t(sigma)ge t(tau)$.
$t(sigma0)perp t(sigma1)$.
But then the set $${t(0), t(10), t(110), t(1110), ...}$$ forms an infinite strong antichain in $mathbb{P}$.
In fact, we can do even better (since having only finite strong antichains is preserved by passing from $mathbb{P}$ to $mathbb{P}_{le s}$):
If $mathbb{P}$ has only finite strong antichains, then the set of "trivializing" $p$ is dense in $mathbb{P}$; so every $mathbb{P}$-generic filter is already in the ground model. (And consequently, we have "${bf MA(aleph_0,infty)}$.")
So such a poset really is trivial (in the sense of forcing), not just "possibly trivial," as is the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom.
Thanks. It was my intuition that the problem would trivilize like that, but I hadn't yet matured the subject enough to prove it.
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
add a comment |
The issue is that a poset where all strong antichains have finite width is trivial - at least, as far as forcing is concerned - and so the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom is trivial too.
To see that such forcings are trivial, the key point is the following:
Let $mathbb{P}$ be a poset with an element $p$ such that every $q_1,q_2le p$ have a common extension $r$ (that is, $p$ doesn't bound any nontrivial strong antichain). Then there is a $mathbb{P}$-generic filter in the ground model already.
The proof is simple: let $G$ be the set of all conditions compatible with $p$.
Now suppose $mathbb{P}$ is a poset where every strong antichain is finite. I claim that $mathbb{P}$ has such a "trivializing" element $p$. For if not, we can inductively define a map $t$ from $2^{<omega}$ to $mathbb{P}$ such that:
$sigmaprectauimplies t(sigma)ge t(tau)$.
$t(sigma0)perp t(sigma1)$.
But then the set $${t(0), t(10), t(110), t(1110), ...}$$ forms an infinite strong antichain in $mathbb{P}$.
In fact, we can do even better (since having only finite strong antichains is preserved by passing from $mathbb{P}$ to $mathbb{P}_{le s}$):
If $mathbb{P}$ has only finite strong antichains, then the set of "trivializing" $p$ is dense in $mathbb{P}$; so every $mathbb{P}$-generic filter is already in the ground model. (And consequently, we have "${bf MA(aleph_0,infty)}$.")
So such a poset really is trivial (in the sense of forcing), not just "possibly trivial," as is the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom.
The issue is that a poset where all strong antichains have finite width is trivial - at least, as far as forcing is concerned - and so the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom is trivial too.
To see that such forcings are trivial, the key point is the following:
Let $mathbb{P}$ be a poset with an element $p$ such that every $q_1,q_2le p$ have a common extension $r$ (that is, $p$ doesn't bound any nontrivial strong antichain). Then there is a $mathbb{P}$-generic filter in the ground model already.
The proof is simple: let $G$ be the set of all conditions compatible with $p$.
Now suppose $mathbb{P}$ is a poset where every strong antichain is finite. I claim that $mathbb{P}$ has such a "trivializing" element $p$. For if not, we can inductively define a map $t$ from $2^{<omega}$ to $mathbb{P}$ such that:
$sigmaprectauimplies t(sigma)ge t(tau)$.
$t(sigma0)perp t(sigma1)$.
But then the set $${t(0), t(10), t(110), t(1110), ...}$$ forms an infinite strong antichain in $mathbb{P}$.
In fact, we can do even better (since having only finite strong antichains is preserved by passing from $mathbb{P}$ to $mathbb{P}_{le s}$):
If $mathbb{P}$ has only finite strong antichains, then the set of "trivializing" $p$ is dense in $mathbb{P}$; so every $mathbb{P}$-generic filter is already in the ground model. (And consequently, we have "${bf MA(aleph_0,infty)}$.")
So such a poset really is trivial (in the sense of forcing), not just "possibly trivial," as is the corresponding variant of Martin's Axiom.
edited 2 days ago
answered 2 days ago
Noah Schweber
122k10148284
122k10148284
Thanks. It was my intuition that the problem would trivilize like that, but I hadn't yet matured the subject enough to prove it.
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
add a comment |
Thanks. It was my intuition that the problem would trivilize like that, but I hadn't yet matured the subject enough to prove it.
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
Thanks. It was my intuition that the problem would trivilize like that, but I hadn't yet matured the subject enough to prove it.
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
Thanks. It was my intuition that the problem would trivilize like that, but I hadn't yet matured the subject enough to prove it.
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.
Please pay close attention to the following guidance:
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3060799%2ffinite-chain-condition-variation-of-martins-axiom-statement%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
You're missing/ignoring the requirement that the forcing notions must be separative.
– Not Mike
2 days ago
1
@NotMike I'm very new to this, and I don't understand why is that required in any sense for any of my statements/questions
– Emilio Martinez
2 days ago
2
Replacing "ccc" by uncountable cardinals is a very difficult problem. Recently James Cummings, Mirna Dzamonja, and Itay Neeman have proposed a nice generalization. You can find it on arXiv. Other than this, you'd venture well into generalized properness, which is depressingly convoluted and hard to understand, main works are by Shelah and Roslanowski.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
2
I mean that there are a lot inherent difficulties in forcing axioms which do not revolve around $omega$ in some significant way.
– Asaf Karagila♦
2 days ago
1
The point is not to "just change ccc", but also to get something which is consistent and helpful in proving similar consequences to what MA provides us with.
– Asaf Karagila♦
5 hours ago